Johnson LS. The Case for Reasonable Accommodation of
Conscientious Objections
to Declarations of Brain Death. J Bioeth Inq. 2016 Jan 5.
[Epub ahead of print]
Abstract
Since its inception in 1968, the concept of whole-brain
death has been contentious, and four decades on, controversy concerning the
validity and coherence of whole-brain death continues unabated. Although
whole-brain death is legally recognized and medically entrenched in the United
States and elsewhere, there is reasonable disagreement among physicians,
philosophers, and the public concerning whether brain death is really
equivalent to death as it has been traditionally understood. A handful of
states have acknowledged this plurality of viewpoints and enacted
"conscience clauses" that require "reasonable
accommodation" of religious and moral objections to the determination of
death by neurological criteria. This paper argues for the universal adoption of
"reasonable accommodation" policies using the New Jersey statute as a
model, in light of both the ongoing controversy and the recent case of Jahi
McMath, a child whose family raised religious objections to a declaration of
brain death. Public policies that accommodate reasonable, divergent viewpoints
concerning death provide a practical and compassionate way to resolve those
conflicts that are the most urgent, painful, and difficult to reconcile.
________________________________________________________________
From the manuscript:
This paper will argue for universal adoption of reasonable
accommodation policies modelled on New Jersey’s statute. First, I’ll assess
whether there is reasonable disagreement when it comes to whole-brain death by
examining current medical and philosophical controversies concerning the
determination of death. Next, I’ll discuss the Jahi McMath case, in which the
family of a teenaged girl in California raised religious objections to a
declaration of death by neurological criteria. I’ll then examine existing
“reasonable accommodation” policies in California, New York, and New Jersey,
and consider how “reasonable accommodation” in defining death might be
interpreted by looking at the “reasonable person” standard and federal laws
that mandate “reasonable accommodation” in other contexts, and also consider
the question of to whom reasonable accommodation applies. I’ll then consider
what definitions of death might be prima facie reasonable and merit
accommodation. Finally, I'll show why reasonable accommodation is needed, and
how a conscience clause modelled on New Jersey’s statute can respect plurality
and diversity, avoid conflicts over the determination of death, and have other
ethically significant salutary effects as well…
Since its inception, the concept of brain death has been
contentious, and pronouncements of the impending death of brain death have been
frequent. While whole-brain death is decidedly a matter of settled law, both in
the United States and elsewhere, the matter has hardly been settled from a
medical, moral, or philosophical standpoint.
Brain death is deeply counterintuitive and defies
traditional, common-sense notions of life and death…
It is little wonder that the tongue must be tied in knots to
speak of the “brain dead.” The council refers to the “brain dead” patient as a
“heart-beating cadaver” exhibiting “something like health,” with a mechanical
ventilator “in essence, ventilating a corpse–albeit one that in many ways does
not look like a corpse”. It is difficult, in the face of medical evidence and
common sense, to maintain that brain death is really, truly death, but there is
ample evidence that whole-brain death is not even really, truly indicative of a
completely dead brain.
The question Is there reasonable disagreement about
whole-brain death? can be answered in the affirmative. Although the orthodox
medical and legal position is that whole-brain death is death, there remains
considerable and reasonable disagreement and doubt about defining death by
neurological criteria….
New Jersey’s law is the only one in the United States to
mandate that if a patient objects on religious grounds to neurological criteria
for determining death, then death “shall be declared and the time of death
fixed, solely upon the cardio-respiratory criteria”. That is, when there is a
religious objection to the use of neurological criteria, the patient is not
considered legally dead unless and until there is an irreversible cessation of
all circulatory and respiratory function. Moreover, the law prohibits health
insurance providers from denying coverage on the basis of brain death when
there is a religious objection, thus removing the potential for financial
conflicts of interest for hospitals and financial coercion of families facing
decisions concerning the withdrawal of life support. New Jersey’s law, unlike
New York’s and California’s, specifically privileges religious objections, but
not other conscientious objections. Despite this omission, its provisions are
uniquely and genuinely accommodating of conscientious differences in the
determination of death…
If providers and hospitals are under no obligation to allow
for an alternative definition of death, they can pay little more than lip
service to “reasonable accommodation,” and families and patients have little
choice but to acquiesce. That was certainly evident in the Jahi McMath case,
where, following the hospital’s declaration of death, a death certificate was
issued, and the child’s still-breathing “corpse” was released to the coroner
rather than her family. These are not practices enacted when patients are
alive. Since Jahi McMath was declared medically and legally dead and, under
California law, she “is dead,” it can hardly be said that the family’s views
regarding the definition of death were accommodated at all. The sole accommodation
afforded the family, per court order, paradoxically supports their contention
that Jahi is not dead: she remained on ventilatory support before, during, and
after she was transferred to the coroner, a practice that is hardly standard
when dealing with cadavers…
There exists reasonable disagreement about the adequacy,
coherence, and validity of whole-brain death. Well-informed, reasonable people
dissent from the whole-brain-death orthodoxy, and there is compelling evidence
that brain death is not death as it has been long and commonly understood.
Brain death is counter-intuitive, defies common sense, and runs counter to the
religious beliefs of many people in a number of religions that, taken together,
represent a significant segment of the world’s population. Genuine
conscientious objections to declarations of death using neurological criteria
in the United States must too frequently be adjudicated in court at
considerable cost to families, healthcare providers, and taxpayers. These
disputes also cause significant and prolonged emotional distress to families
already struggling with the loss of a loved one.
The stakes are extremely high in disputes concerning
declarations of brain death and the definition of death because the debate is,
in essence, over the moral status of a human being. To declare that someone is
dead is to say they are no longer a person with full moral and legal rights and
no longer entitled to the care they would receive if we considered them to be
living members of the moral community. The debate is, then, a moral debate that
will not be resolved by science alone. No technological advance, no brain scan,
or neurological test will settle the matter once and for all. Similarly, laws
that endorse whole-brain death as death will not settle the matter, especially
in those parts of the world like North America and Europe that are increasingly
heterogeneous and home to people of diverse religious and cultural traditions
and moral convictions. In a pluralistic society, consensus will not be forged
or forced by either law or medicine when it comes to the definition of death…
The optimal solution is a compromise, one that does not
scrap the currently accepted definitions of circulatory-respiratory death and
whole-brain death, but rather permits conscientious objections to declarations
of brain death through reasonable accommodation statutes. The optimal solution
should not create or accept a situation of complete cultural or ethical
relativism in which any and all definitions of death are equally valid and
endorsed by law and public policy. Indeed, the two existing definitions of
death should suffice, for they already include the most viable, least
controversial, alternative to brain death. Circulatory-respiratory death is a
legally and medically sound, reasonable definition of death, and one that
enjoys near universal acceptance across cultures and religions. It can
reasonably be accommodated as an alternative to brain death, and, as I have
argued, it would be unreasonable and unethical to refuse to accommodate it…
It is the decent and compassionate thing to allow a grieving
family to be reconciled with the loss of a loved one on terms they can accept,
without the threat of medical neglect or unilateral withdrawal of life support.
Whether Jahi McMath is alive or dead may be in dispute, but there is no
question that a family has lost a beloved child, a child who will never again
be as she once was. Children’s Hospital Oakland used its time and resources to
fight McMath’s family in court and repeatedly and publicly referred to the
child as “a deceased person” and a “dead body” (BBC 2013). But if Jahi had
“died” in New Jersey instead of California, she would still be alive, both in
the eyes of her family and under the law.
The controversies over brain death are unlikely to be
resolved in the near future, but adopting public policies that accommodate
reasonable, divergent viewpoints concerning death provides a practical and
compassionate way to resolve conflicts that are urgent, painful, and resistant
to reconciliation.
No comments:
Post a Comment